Can Change the World Again. |
BY JAMES ARMINIUS.
I CANNOT easily describe, most excellent sir, with how much
delight I was affected by reading and seriously considering
your commentary on the 9th chapter of the Epistle to the
Romans. For when I saw that your idea of the scope of the
Apostle, and of the use of his principle arguments, was the
same, as I had recently presented to my congregation, in
explaining the same chapter, I was greatly confirmed in that
opinion, both because I have great confidence in your
judgment, and because I found proofs in the arguments, which
you advanced. I could not, therefore, do less than to write,
in return, to you to present my thanks, and to inform you how
I have proceeded in explaining this chapter, and what
impelled me to take this course; not to prove our mutual
agreement only, but to confirm it as much as is in my power.
I candidly confess that this chapter has always seemed to me
to be involved in the greatest obscurity, and its explanation
has appeared most difficult, until light, introduced in this
way, dispelled the shades, and placed the subject,
illustrated by its own clearness, before my mind, so as to be
plainly understood.
I come to the subject itself. In the first place, the scope
of the chapter is the same with that of the whole epistle:
That the Gospel, not the law, is the power of God unto
salvation, not to him that worketh, but to him that
believeth, since, in the Gospel the righteousness of God is
manifested in the obtainment of salvation by faith in Christ.
This chapter performs its part, and indeed is peculiarly
engaged in the support of that proposition. It defends the
proposition against the objections of the Jews, who, with all
their power endeavour to overturn it as hostile and
destructive to their own views, and so defends it as to
confirm its truth more and more, and, by refuting those
objections, adds strength and stability to the foundation
already laid, in that very divine word and purpose, which the
Jews were strenuously wresting, in their own favour, to the
overthrow of Paul's doctrine.
That such is the design of the chapter, the connection shows,
the relation of which may be sought, partly from this
antecedent proposition. Many of the Jews are cast off, which
is included, also, in the introduction of this chapter -- "I
could wish that myself were accursed from Christ for my
brethren," partly from the negation contained in the sixth
verse -- "Not as though the word of God hath taken none
effect." Both of which, being embraced in one enunciation,
may be suitably rendered thus -- Though most of the Jews are
rejected, yet the word of God does not therefore fail. Hence
it appears, most clearly, that the Jews had made an
assertion, against Paul, opposed to this negation, that, by
the interposition of that antecedent, (which was,
immediately, deduced from the doctrine of Paul) they might
convict that doctrine, from which a consequence so absurd
might be deduced, of falsity, and refute it as absurd, in
this manner: -- "If most of the Jews are rejected, the word
of God must fail; -- But it can not be that the word of God
should fail; -- Therefore, most of the Jews are not
rejected." How does this operate against the apostle? He had
proposed a doctrine, which necessarily included the rejection
of the Jews to a very considerable extent, namely,
righteousness and salvation are to be obtained by faith in
Christ, not by the works of the law. It was easy for the Jews
to deduce from this, -- "If righteousness and salvation
consist in faith in Christ, whom Paul preaches, it follows
that the Jews, for the most part, are rejected from the
covenant." The reason of this conclusion is this. "Because
most of the Jews do not believe in Christ." But it is false
that most of the Jews are rejected by God; for then the word
of God would fail. Therefore, the doctrine of the apostle
Paul, from which that consequence is deduced, is absurd. The
apostle considered that it was necessary for them to refute
this objection, which threatened overthrow and destruction to
his doctrine, by showing that the undoubted principle, which
the Jews used as the prop of their objection, was not only
not injurious to his cause, but even very favourable to it.
It is necessary to properly settle the state of the question
in controversy between the apostle and the Jews. For this
will be of great importance to the whole matter. It is not --
"are most of the Jews rejected?" or -- "Is the word of God of
none effect?" For the apostle confesses that it would be
impious even to admit the latter thought. The former he will
afterwards prove by the clear testimony of the Scripture. But
the question embraces both these; -- "Will the word of God
fail, even if most of the Jews are rejected?" Even this is
not sufficient. The answer of this question does not settle
the whole dispute, or exhaust all the difficulties. For, if
the apostle, by the force of his arguments, should gain this
point, that some, and indeed most of the Jews, are rejected,
and yet the word of God remains sure, would not this question
remain: "Does not the word of God fail, if those of the Jews
are rejected, who, with the greatest zeal, seek the
righteousness of the Law?" That question must still remain,
as it would be easy for the Jews to make an exception to the
solution of that question -- "Though the word of God may
remain sure, if many of the Jews are rejected, yet we can not
be included in the number, else the word of God would fail."
This element, therefore, having been added, will complete the
entire statement of the question, thus: "Does not the word
God become of none effect, if those of the Jews, who seek
righteousness, not of faith, but of the law, are rejected by
God."
This question is suited to his design; the solution of this
finishes the discussion, and exhausts all the difficulties;
of this the apostle treats, as is evident from his arguments,
which all bear upon its solution. Nor indeed is that, which
gave rise to the question, to be separated from the question,
and to refute which that principle having reference to the
certainty of the word of God, was adduced by the Jews, and
which the apostle also endeavoured, as strongly as possible,
to assert against them. In this question, therefore, this is
to be chiefly attended to, -- "would the word of the
covenant, entered into with the Jews, be in vain, if the
doctrine of the apostle in reference to the attainment of
righteousness and salvation by faith alone in Christ, not by
the law, or the works of the law, should find a place, and
should be regarded as the fundamental principle of
salvation?" How much difference exists between those two
conditions of the question, and of how much importance that
difference is, you readily see. For the question, proposed in
this mode, "would not the word of God be vain, if most of the
Jews are rejected?" could be answered in this way. "God
indeed, in the word of promise, invited all the Jews and
called them to a participation of the covenant, but yet, by
His eternal decree and purpose, He determined in fact to make
only some of the Jews partakers, passing by the rest, and
leaving them in their former state." Some indeed say that
this is the sum of the answer of the apostle to the proposed
question. But the question, proposed in this last manner, --
"Would not the word of God fail, if those of the Jews, who
seek righteousness, not of faith, but of the law, are
rejected by God?" -- can only be answered in this way. "God,
in His word, and in the declaration of His promise, signified
that He considered, in the relation of children, only, those
of the Jews, who should seek righteousness and salvation by
faith, but in the relation of foreigners, those who should
seek the same by the law." But the two answers are very
different. In the former, the decree of Predestination is
defined according to the sentiment of Beza and others; in the
latter, according to your sentiment. Far be it from me,
however, to make a statement such as to confirm your view or
my own concerning the decree of Predestination by the answer,
which I see to be alone adapted to the question so stated.
The passage itself will, indeed, declare, if examined, that
the state of the question is that, which I have presented, if
a right judgment can really be formed, concerning the state
of the question, from the. arguments adduced in its
discussion, and from the conclusion arrived at, which no one
will deny, who has ever saluted the threshold of knowledge.
Let us, then, consider these points, in the answer of the
apostle. First, he denies that the consequence -- "the word
of God fails" -- can, in any way, be deduced from the
antecedent, which the Jews proposed: in these words -- "Not
as though the word of God hath taken none effect." Then he
subjoins the reason of the denial, and the Scriptural proof,
interwoven with the reason by means of allegories, dictated
by God, and explained by the apostle. The reason consists in
the distinction of the Jews, and their two-fold
classification, in respect to this divine word and purpose,
or from the two-fold seed of Abraham, of which only one was
comprehended in that word and purpose. "For," he says, "they
are not all Israel which are of Israel: Neither because they
are the seed of Abraham, are they all children:" but there
are, among them, some "children of the flesh" and others
"children of the promise;" whence it is concluded -- If the
word of God does not embrace all the Israelites in one
character, it does not fail, even if some, from their number,
may be rejected; and much less, if they are rejected of whom
it is evident, from the word itself, that they never were
comprehended in it. This indeed ought altogether to be added,
or the question can in no way be satisfied. It was, indeed,
added, as is apparent from the apostle. Nor, indeed, does he
only say that not all are comprehended under that word, but
he describes those, who are considered as children by God,
and who are not included in that term. For the children of
the flesh are considered, by the apostle, alien from the
covenant, and the children of the promise are considered
partakers of the covenant. Hence this argument, refuting
Jewish objection, may be constructed. If the word of God
comprehends only the children of the promise, to the
exclusion of the children of the flesh, then it follows that
the word of God does not fail, even if the children of the
flesh are rejected: it, indeed, would fail if they should be
received, who are excluded by the very condition of the
covenant; -- But the word of God comprehends only the
children of the promise, to the exclusion of the children of
the flesh; -- Therefore, the word of God does not fail, even
if the children of the flesh are rejected. By consequence,
also; -- The word of God does not fail, even if most of the
Jews are rejected, provided they are embraced in the number
of the children of the flesh, and that they are so included
is evident from the description of the children of the flesh.
The children of the flesh are said, in this place, by the
apostle, to be those who, by the works of the law, follow
after righteousness and salvation. In this way, also, the
consequent is sustained, being deduced from his doctrine
concerning justification and salvation by faith in Christ.
For it does not follow from this, that some of the Jews are
rejected, unless by this distinguishing mark, namely, that
they do not believe in Christ, but follow after the
righteousness of the law. But the children of the promise are
they, who seek righteousness and salvation by faith in
Christ. This description of the children of the flesh and of
the promise is so plain from the Scriptures, as not to need
further argument. But the foundations of the proofs can be
sought from the 4th, 9th, and 10th chapters of this epistle,
and from the 3d and 4th chapters of the Epistle to the
Galatians, as you have observed, and as I presented to my
congregation, when I treated this subject.
From this discussion of the question it is evident, that it
must be proposed in the second manner, with reference to the
character of those rejected. We must now, indeed, consider
the proof of that reason, which is assumed in the refutatory
syllogism. For the consequence, deduced from it, is, in
itself, clear and manifest. The apostle, then, proves that
the word of the promise and covenant comprehends only the
children of the promise, to the exclusion of the children of
the flesh, and this by a two-fold type, one, taken from the
family of Abraham, and the other from the family of Isaac.
But two things are to be presupposed to the argument in both
cases, both supported by the authority of the apostle, which
ought to be held sacred by us. One, that Ishmael and Isaac,
Esau and Jacob, are to be considered, not in themselves, but
as types in those passages, which he presents. The other,
that they are types of the children of the flesh and of the
promise. The apostle proves neither, but assumes both and
correctly. For it is most certain, from an inspection of the
passages themselves, that this is so, for the apostle says,
in Gal. iv, 24, "which things are an allegory," and that the
first sense, which God wished to give in those passages, is
not literal, but allegorical. These things being presupposed,
the force of the apostle's argument consists in the agreement
between the types and antitypes, which is as great as is the
immutability and constancy of Him, who willed that these
should be the types, corresponding to those antitypes. But it
is to be observed that this agreement consists, not in their
exact resemblance, but in their mutual connection and
relation, the proper difference of type and antitype being
preserved. I give this admonition that no one may think it
necessary that he, who represents the children of the flesh,
should himself be a child of the flesh, by the mode of the
same definition. Now, to the particular cases. The proof from
the first type depends on these two passages of Scripture
(verses 7 and 9). "In Isaac shall thy seed be called," and
"at this time will I come, and Sarah shall have a son." From
which this argument is deduced, that agreement being
presupposed; -- In the seed, reference is made to Isaac; --
But Isaac is the type of all the children of the promise; --
Therefore, all the children of the promise are regarded in
the seed. The Major is embraced in these words -- "In Isaac
shall thy seed be called." The Minor, partly in these words -
- "For this is the word of promise, At this time will I come,
and Sarah shall have a son;" partly in that agreement, of
which mention was made.
But not only may we infer that all the children of the
promise are reckoned in the seed, but that they alone are so
reckoned. For those things, which are spoken of Isaac, are
effectual to the exclusion of Ishmael, as the apostle
signifies by the adversative particle "but" (7th verse),
joined to the member of the sentence, opposed to the former
negations, "but, In Isaac shall thy seed be called;" from
which this conclusion is deduced; -- Ishmael is not reckoned
in the seed; -- But Ishmael is the type of all the children
of the flesh; -- Therefore, none of the children of the flesh
are reckoned in the seed. I know that in that figure, the
conclusion is deduced only in a particular case, but the
strength of the conclusion depends on the agreement, which
subsists between the type, and that which is adumbrated by
the type, in accordance with the immutable will of God. We
know, also, that a conclusion may be drawn from the necessity
of the subject, which can not be drawn from the particular
form of the syllogism. Here we might say many things
concerning the consequent mode of the mutual relation of
Ishmael and the children of the flesh, and of Isaac, and the
children of the promise; and how this was aptly signified by
the birth of each, as the apostle declares was prefigured by
that type. But I think that it is unnecessary to repeat those
things, because they serve only to explain that sentiment,
not to confirm it, as it is sufficiently proved to us by the
authority of the apostle, namely, that the children of the
flesh are signified by Ishmael, but the children of the
promise, by Isaac.
Now another type is introduced, taken from the family of
Isaac, in which the apostle affirms that the same thing is
declared, as in the former, when he says (10th verse) "and
not only this, but when Rebecca, also, &c." That passage,
therefore, adduced for the same purpose, is to be explained
in accordance with the same design. But three things are to
be considered here, in order. First -- some circumstances,
peculiar to this type, which add much weight to the proof of
the apostle, and by which the apostle anticipates whatever he
foresees can be brought forward by the Jews against the
former type in opposition to his cause. Secondly -- the word
of God, which was addressed to Rebecca, which the typical
argument embraces, is illustrated from another passage, taken
from one of the prophets. Thirdly -- the explanation which
Paul, the divinely inspired, gives of the object and scope of
that divine declaration.
As to the first, the Jews could object against the former
type, that it is not wonderful that Ishmael, being rejected,
Isaac should be adopted as a son by God, both because Ishmael
was the child of a bond woman, and Isaac of the free woman,
and because, before God announced the word of promise to
Sarah, Ishmael was born and could have perpetrated those
things which made him unworthy of that honour and felicity.
The apostle meets these objections, and replies to the first,
that, in the case of Esau and Jacob, the circumstances were
entirely different, as they had both the same father and the
same mother, and were born at the same birth. In reply to the
second objection, he refers to the words, addressed to
Rebecca, when she was yet carrying the twins in her womb, and
therefore, the children were not yet born, and could not have
done any good or evil, by which one deserved to be rejected
and the other adopted. By these circumstances, the Jews were
deprived of any objection, which they could make against the
previous type, namely, that they, being born of the free
woman, and seeking their salvation from the law, could, in no
way whatever, be reckoned among those who were rejected.
Those words, addressed to Rebecca, are to be considered,
which were briefly these: "The elder shall serve the
younger." They are explained by a passage from Mal. i, 2, 3.
"Jacob have I loved, but Esau have I hated," and this is
said, that it may be evident that the servitude of the elder
is united with the divine hatred, and the dominion of the
younger with the divine love.
Here we must repeat what was said before, as a general
remark, that Esau and Jacob are to be considered, not in
themselves, but as types, and so that which is attributed to
them, is to be accommodated to the antitypes, or rather to
the things signified. Hence, also, the antitypes are to be
considered, before a conclusion, similar to the former, can
be deduced from them, to the refutation of the sentiment of
the Jews and to the confirmation of that of the apostle. But
what those antitypes are, may be gathered from the end or
design which the apostle has added, in these words: "that the
purpose of God, according to election, might stand, not of
works, but of Him that calleth." That is, God, in those
words, "the elder shall serve the younger," addressed to
Rebecca, "the children being not yet born, neither having
done any good or evil," designed to indicate nothing else
than that He had formed, in His own mind, from eternity, a
purpose to communicate righteousness and salvation, not one
which should embrace all the posterity of Abraham
universally, but which should be according to election, by
which He would distinguish between these and those, not
considered simply in their own nature, as pure or corrupt,
but in respect to the condition, by which righteousness and
salvation were to be applied, as the apostle shows in the
following words -- that this purpose, according to election,
might stand not of works, but of him who calleth, in which
words is contained a description of the antitypes, which had
before been given in the phrases "children of the flesh" and
"children of the promise." Here it is more clear, for the
children of the flesh and those of the promise are, such, by
their own peculiarity, defined by the apostle, in this
passage, since the former are "of works," the latter of
faith, by which obedience is rendered unto God, who
"calleth." Therefore, the apostle says that the purpose of
God, which is according to election, has reference to those
who have faith in God who calleth, and who trust in Christ,
not to those who seek salvation by the works of the law. The
conclusion can be drawn from these things against the
objection of the Jews in favour of the doctrine of the
apostle concerning justification by faith, in this way: "If
the word of God and His purpose is according to election, by
which the former is rejected, and the latter accepted, then
it follows, even if some of the Jews are rejected, yet that
word and purpose is not in vain; rather indeed, if that
purpose, which is according to election, should be said to
embrace all without any election, it would be in vain; -- But
this word and purpose is according to election; Therefore,
even if some of the Jews should be rejected, yet that word
and purpose does not, on that account, fail; it is, indeed,
rather confirmed from that fact, because it is its nature to
exclude some, as it is according to election, by which one is
rejected and another accepted."
An indefinite proof of this kind, however, is not sufficient
for this subject: for it remains to be proved that those same
persons are excluded by the purpose according to election,
who are properly considered to be excluded and rejected,
according to the doctrine of the apostle concerning
justification by faith, namely, those who sought to obtain
righteousness and salvation, not from faith in Christ, but
from the works of the law. This, therefore, the apostle adds.
Hence to exhaust the whole objection, the conclusion is drawn
thus: If the purpose, according to election, stands, not of
works, but of Him that calleth, then it follows that they,
who seek after righteousness and salvation from the works of
the law, and by the law, are not included in that purpose,
but they, only, who by faith obey God, who promiseth and
calleth; -- But the purpose, according to election, stands,
not of works, but of Him that calleth; -- Therefore, in that
purpose, they are not embraced, who are of the law, but only
they who are of the faith of Jesus Christ. The Major is, in
itself, plain from its phraseology, if rightly understood,
which signifies that the firmness of the purpose, which is
according to election, depends, not on works, but on Him that
calleth. Therefore, to them who are of the works of the law,
this purpose can not be firm and sure, but to those who are
of faith.
From this idea, I seem to myself to perceive the reason that
God placed the condition of the covenant of grace, not in a
perfect obedience to the law, as previously, but in faith in
Christ. The minor depends on the declaration "the elder shall
serve the younger," and on the agreement of the type and
antitype, which consists in this -- that what is presignified
by the type should correspond to the antitype. But, by the
type of Esau and Jacob, is presignified, first, that the
purpose of God is according to election; then, that this
purpose stands, not of works, but of Him that calleth. The
former, indeed, because one was loved and the other hated;
one was preferred to and placed over the other, which is a
sign of "the purpose according to election;" the latter,
because Esau, the elder, was hated and made subject, and
Jacob, the younger, was loved, and placed over him, which is
a sign that this purpose stands, "not of works, but of Him
that calleth;" that is, that God loves them, who seek
righteousness, and salvation by faith in Christ, but hates
them who seek the same by the works of the law. It follows
that they are not embraced in that purpose, who are of the
works of the law, but only they who are of the faith of Jesus
Christ, and consequently that those of the Jews are rejected,
who followed the righteousness of the law, and they are
elected and loved, who sought participation in righteousness
by faith in Christ. Therefore, so far from the truth is it
that this doctrine of justification by faith is overthrown by
the word of the covenant and the divine purpose, that, by
this, alone, it is established.
At this point, I have also explained to many, how the Jews
were signified by Esau, the elder, who were seeking, in their
zeal for the law, justification and life by the law, and
that, by Jacob, the younger, they were signified, who sought
the same things by faith in Christ. It is not necessary to
repeat these things here; the authority of the apostle is
sufficient, who thus explains those types, and who, briefly,
from the agreement of the type and antitype, or that which is
signified by the type, deduces this argument. Esau, the
elder, was condemned to be the servant of his brother, by
God, and was hated by him; -- But Esau, the elder, is the
type of all those who seek justification and salvation by the
works of the law; -- Therefore, all they who seek salvation
by the works of the law, are condemned to servitude, and are
hated by God. Again; -- Jacob, the younger, obtained dominion
over his brother, and was loved by God; -- Jacob, the
younger, is the type of all those who, according to the grace
of vocation, by faith seek justification. Therefore, they
who, according to the grace of vocation, by faith seek
justification, obtain dominion, and are loved by God. Both
Majors are included in the declarations "The elder shall
serve the younger" and "Jacob have I loved, but Esau have I
hated" The Minors are contained in these words, "that the
purpose of God, according to election, might stand, not of
works, but of Him that calleth," and depend on the authority
of the apostle, who thus explains those types.
Hence it is apparent that the question referred not only to
the rejection of some and the acceptance of others, but to
the rejection or acceptance of those of certain characters,
that is, those distinguished by certain qualities. Therefore
the apostle, here, treats not of the decree or the divine
purpose, by which some are elected and others are reprobated,
considered absolutely in their own nature, whether pure or
corrupt; but of a purpose such as includes that description
of elect and reprobate, which is here clearly observed in
that purpose by the apostle: in which consists, in fact, the
controversy between Beza with his followers, who strenuously
defend the former and yourself, who urge a purpose of
salvation such as to embrace the characters of those, who are
to be saved and those who are to be damned.
But they will say that it is indeed true that Ishmael and
Esau, Isaac and Jacob are to be considered typically, that
is, the former, in each case, representing the character of
the children of the flesh, and of those who ale of the works
of the law, and the latter, the children of the promise, and
those who are of faith, but that they also, for themselves,
belong, in the same manner, to those classes, which they
typify, and this of the eternal purpose of God, by which He
determined to make Isaac and Jacob children of the promise,
and to bestow on them faith in Christ, but to leave Ishmael
and Esau in the carnal nature, in which they were born.
They affirm that we must go further back and inquire why one
is the child of the flesh, another of the promise, why one
should believe in Christ, and another should not believe, but
seek salvation of the works of the law. I answer -- It can
not be proved from this passage that they, who are types,
pertain to the antitypes: and if it may, perhaps, be true
that Ishmael and Esau belong to the children of the flesh, as
thus described, yet that they are such, of any divine
purpose, is not taught in this place. In this purpose, as we
have explained it, something is determined concerning the
children of the flesh and of the promise, but with the
explanation which they prefer, something is determined
concerning individuals, that these should be children of the
flesh, those of the promise. They can not, therefore, be the
same purposes, the subject of one being changed into the
attribute of the other. Concerning the adequate subject,
there is not, as yet, harmony even among the Coryphaei of
that view. And since the question -- "why do some believe and
others not?" has the same change of subject and attribute, I
affirm that it is not here discussed by the apostle, nor has
it even the least connection with his design. They must
therefore, consult other passages of Scripture and see
whether they can, from them, obtain proof for that decree. It
is sufficient for us that, here, the purpose is described, by
which our justification and salvation through grace, may be
self consistent, and by which we can be made more certain, in
ourselves, concerning the same things. But this purpose is
that which God determined, after the former condition added
to the legal covenant had not been performed, and man had by
the fall been made unable to perform it, to enter into a
covenant of grace with us through Christ; and of grace to
change the condition of the former covenant into faith in
Christ, by which we, believing in Christ, might obtain the
same thing as we should have previously obtained by plenary
obedience to the law, rendered by ourselves. On this purpose,
as it appears, depends the certainty of our salvation, and at
the same time the assurance of it in ourselves. For we inter
that assurance from this Enthymene, "I am a believer," or "I
believe in Christ; -- therefore I shall be saved," or "I am
elect." The strength of which depends on this proposition:
"God has immutably determined from eternity to save those,
who believe Christ;" in which words is contained the sum of
that purpose.
If any one should inquire, "Why did God wish that Ishmael and
Esau should be the types of the children of the flesh, but
Isaac and Jacob the types of the children of the promise?" I
answer -- Because it was suitable for the sake of
significancy, and of agreement between the type and the
antitype; in relation to the former type that he who was born
of the bond woman and of the flesh should be the type of the
children of the flesh, but that he, who was born of the free
woman, and of the promise, when the flesh had now become
unfruitful, should be the type of the children of the
promise; but in relation to the latter type, that he, who was
born first, should prefigure the children of the flesh, and
he, who was born last, the children of the promise. The
reason will be manifest to those who consider the agreement
of types and antitypes.
It may be asked further, "Why did God will that Ishmael
should be born of the bond woman and of the flesh, and that
Esau should be born first; but that Isaac should be born of
the free woman, and of the promise, and Jacob last?" I reply
that the same question would be asked, if Isaac and Jacob had
been substituted for Ishmael and Esau. In this matter, the
Divine freedom is complete, circumscribed by no necessity of
the Divine attributes, or of His revealed will. This will be
seen of the attributes of the divine nature and His own
revealed will are subject to God, in the determination of
that purpose, for which your opponents contend.
Let us, now, come to another objection, which is of this
character: "What shall we say then? Is there unrighteousness
with God." The nature of this question, and of this objection
is manifest, but it is not equally clear, what the antecedent
is from which that objection is deduced. Some state it thus:
-- "If God, without any respect of works, regards Ishmael and
Esau with hatred and excludes them from the number of His
children, but loves Isaac and Jacob, and considers them as
His children, is He not unjust? It seems to be a kind of
injustice not to bestow the same things on those of the same
character." It is true that, if the apostle was considering
them in themselves, and not as types of certain characters --
as has been remarked -- there would be an occasion for such
an objection. For it is certain that from those antecedents
arises an occasion for the objection. Such, however, was not
the antecedent of the apostle, but this: "God in the word of
the covenant, and in the purpose, which is according to
election, embraced only those, who might be the children of
the promise, who should believe in Christ, to the exclusion
of the children of the flesh and of those who sought the
righteousness of the law." Whence it followed "that those of
the Jews were rejected who, in their zeal for the
righteousness of the law, did not believe in Christ, and,
moreover, those of the Gentiles, who sought a participation
in justification and salvation by faith in Christ, were
received into the covenant." There is besides another
antecedent of that objection, namely, this: "If God hates the
children of the flesh, and excludes them from the covenant,
but loves the children of the promise, and reckons them in
the seed, embraced in the covenant, and this, indeed, of His
mere purpose, without respect to works, then it follows that
He is unjust;" or this: "If God rejects the Jews, and accepts
the Gentiles in their place, then He is unjust." But these
two amount to almost the same thing. I think that the
reasoning of the former is the more conclusive. The reasoning
of this objection seems sufficient to prove injustice in the
Deity, because He made this decree of the mere good pleasure
of His will, without any reference to merit.
Let us, however, examine the answer of the apostle. He first
denies the inference. Then he gives the reason for his
denial. He denies the inference, when He says, "God forbid,"
that is, we ought by no means to admit the thought that there
is injustice in God, who is just in Himself, and, indeed, is
essential justice, and does nothing, and can do nothing,
unless it most perfectly agrees with His nature.
The reason of this denial of the inference is two-fold;
first, from the liberty of the divine mercy; secondly, from
the due illustration of the divine power and glory. That,
which is inferred from the liberty of the divine mercy, is
comprehended in these words, "For He saith to Moses, I will
have mercy on whom I will have mercy, and I will have
compassion on whom I will have compassion" (15th verse). In
these words is expressed, according to the Hebrew idiom, this
idea: "In the choice and liberty of my will is placed the
power of having mercy on whom I will:" as is also indicated
by the deduction, "Therefore hath He mercy on whom He will
have mercy" (verse 18th). But in what way this answer is
effectual to the overthrow of that inference, the word Mercy
declares, which word embraces in itself the whole weight of
the refutation. For the only sufficient reason for charging
injustice on God on account of that purpose was this: that
God could not, without injustice, make of none effect "His
purpose of creation, by which He made justification and life
dependent on obedience to the law, but condemnation and death
in the transgression of the same law; especially so far as to
exclude, from justification and life, those, who should
endeavour, by the law, to attain to justification and life,
but to make others, who should not indeed do this, but should
believe in Christ, partakers of justification and life." This
charge of injustice can be removed from the Deity, only by
the word mercy, here used, which, as it presupposes misery
and sin, by this very fact indicates that a change of the
purpose is not made with any blame on God, but because the
condition of that purpose had been violated by a
transgression of the law, and, thus, an inability to keep the
law had been brought upon man. Hence we see that, by the
fault of man, the covenant, entered into at the creation, was
made void, and therefore God, free from its obligation, could
have either punished man according to his demerit, or
instituted another purpose in His own mind. That this might
be for the good of man, it was necessary that mercy should
intervene, which should remit sin, and arrange a condition,
which He might, by the aid of mercy itself, be able to
perform. The apostle affirms that God formed within Himself a
purpose of this character, and this indeed of His mere mercy,
which was free (yet under the guidance of justice) to
determine on whom He might will to have mercy, and on whom He
might will not to have mercy; whom He might will to make
partakers of justification and life, and whom to exclude from
the same blessing. Whence it follows that God, on account of
a decree of this kind, and a purpose according to election,
by which He determined to receive the children of the promise
into the covenant, and exclude from it the children of the
flesh, and which He purposed should stand "not of works, but
of Him that calleth," can not be charged with injustice;
because, moved by mercy alone, He made this decree in His own
mind. God would, therefore, be unjust, if He should deprive
any one of justification and life, or should require a
condition contrary to the covenant entered into at the
creation: but when, on account of the violation of the
condition, and of inability to perform it, it was either for
mercy to make a covenant of grace with man, or for severity
to punish man without hope of pardon; it is apparent that God
was not less free, that indeed He was much more free, to
arrange whatever conditions might seem good to Him, in that
covenant, than in the covenant of creation. Consequently He
could not be charged with injustice in one case more than in
the other.
This whole matter may be treated syllogistically: -- If the
purpose of God according to election to reject the children
of the flesh, but to consider as seed, the children of the
promise has for its cause the mercy and compassion of God
alone; then it follows that God can, by no means, on this
account be charged with injustice; -- But the cause of that
purpose is the mercy of God alone; -- Therefore God can not,
on account of it, be charged with injustice. That this is the
meaning of the answer of the apostle is evident from the
subjoined inferential answer -- "So then it is not of him
that willeth, nor of him that runneth, but of God, that
showeth mercy," (verse 16) supply here "the purpose according
to election," which is effectual so far as he had before said
-- "that the purpose of God, according to election, might
stand, not of works, but of Him that calleth," and "the
children of the promise are counted for seed," the children
of the flesh being excluded. For, when the will and the
course of men are opposed to the mercy of God, it is certain
that the reference is to the effort and the course of a man,
by which he hopes that he will obtain justification and
salvation apart from the mercy of God. Such, however, is the
effort and the course of those, who seek justification and
salvation by the works of the law. When, also, mercy is, on
the other hand, placed in opposition to the will and course
of men, it is evident that the condition of justification and
life, which is most nearly related to mercy, namely, faith in
Christ, the Mediator, is ordained, the other being opposed to
mercy.
The other reason of the denial of the inference consists in
the just illustration of the divine power and glory, in
those, on whom He wills not to have mercy: which, also, is
set forth, in the particular example of Pharaoh. It is
comprehended in these words: "For the Scripture saith unto
Pharaoh, Even for this same purpose have I raised thee up,
that I might shew my power in thee, and that my name might be
declared in all the earth" (verse 17.) From which passage,
the apostle answers that part of the objection, in which God
was charged with injustice because He rejected and regarded
with hatred the children of the flesh, of His purpose
according to election, in an argument, susceptible of the
following form: -- If God is free, for the just declaration
of His own power and the illustration of His own name, to
raise up, harden and punish Pharaoh, then injustice can not
be attributed to God, because, in His purpose according to
election, He decrees to illustrate His own power and glory in
the just hardening and punishment of the children of the
flesh; -- But God was free to do the former, as is apparent
from this passage; -- Therefore also He is free to do the
latter, and hence He can not, on this account, be accused of
injustice. The argument of the Major is valid. For, either
God will be free, in no case, to illustrate the power and
glory of His name in the just punishment of any person, or He
will be, also, free to decree to do this, according to any
purpose, in the condemnation of those, by whose just
condemnation He may will to declare His own power and the
glory of His name.
It is, also, true that to take away the right and power from
God of making a decree, which is according to election, is
nothing else than to be unwilling that He should exhibit His
own power, and the glory of His own name, in the just
hardening and punishment of some men. For these things are
conjoined, to punish any man and to decree that the same man
is obnoxious to punishment. Punishment can be, with justice,
inflicted on no one, unless the same thing was destined for
him by a just purpose or decree. How God was free to raise up
and harden Pharaoh, &c., will be shown hereafter, in the
refutation of a subsequent objection. That this is the whole
meaning of the answer of the apostle appears from the
conclusion, subjoined to the whole answer -- "Therefore hath
He mercy on whom He will have mercy, and whom He will He
hardeneth" (verse 18).
For, by that conclusion, the whole objection of the Jews is
most fully refuted in this way: -- If God can have mercy on
whom He will, and harden whom He will, then He is also free
to form a purpose according to election, by which He may
determine to have mercy on the children of the promise, but
to harden and punish the children of the flesh; -- But God
can have mercy on whom He will, and harden whom He will; --
Therefore He is free to make a decree, according to election,
by which He may determine to have mercy on the children of
the promise, but to harden and punish the children of the
flesh. By consequence, also, if He should do this which He is
free to do, He can not be, at all deservedly, accused of
injustice. Thus the justice of God, in that purpose according
to election, is sustained and proved by the apostle by the
strongest testimonies from the Mosaic Scriptures.
Another objection of the Jews is next presented (19th verse),
arising from the latter part of the conclusion immediately
preceding; in the refutation of which, they who contend for
that absolute decree of God to save certain particular
individuals and to damn others, think that they have strong
support for their cause. On which account, also, we must
diligently examine both the objection and its refutation,
that we may not, by negligence, pass over it, as though it
were unseen: for it is, to them, the club of Hercules, for
conquering all the monsters of objection, or rather the sword
of Alexander, to cut any knot which can not be untied. The
objection is this: "Why doeth he yet find fault?" The reason
of this objection is added: "for who hath resisted his will?"
Which things, proposed in the form of an interrogation, may
be stated thus: "Therefore, He can not justly find fault,
since no one can resist His will." The objection will be
filled up, by the addition of the antecedent, from which this
consequent is deduced: "God hardeneth whom He will."
Therefore, He can not justly find fault with those, who are
hardened. The connective reason between these two is this:
"Since no one has resisted His will." Hence, exists a
continual proposition of this kind -- If no one can resist
the will of God, then He can not justly find fault with
those, whom He hardeneth according to that will.
Let this conditional proposition be converted into a simple
or categorical statement, "God can not justly find fault with
those who are hardened by His own omnipotent will." Such is
the objection. Let us now consider what force it has; that
from the examination, it may be evident how it can be
refuted, and the way for its suitable refutation, may be
prepared. These two things, then, are to be considered.
First, "God can not justly find fault with the hardened."
Second, "Because He has hardened them by His omnipotent will,
which can not be resisted." The examination of the former
consists in the discussion of this question. "Who are they
with whom God can justly find fault?" The examination of the
second consists in the discussion of this: "Whether and in
what manner, they, who are hardened by the omnipotent will of
God, may be exempted from the number of those with whom God
can justly find fault?" The former question will be solved,
if it may be explained, what that is, on account of which God
can justly find fault, that is, what is the proper cause of
the divine anger. The proper cause of the divine anger, and
that, on account of which God can justly find fault with any
one, is sin. But sin is the transgression of a law, that is,
of one which is just, for, if a law be not just, it is not a
law, and therefore, its transgression is not a sin. That a
law may be just, it necessarily requires these two
conditions, that it be enacted by him who has authority to
command, and that it be enacted for him who has the power or
rather ability to obey, not only dunamei but ejnergeia| that
is, has ability of such a character as is hindered by no
intervening decree, from doing that which he can do. Whence
it is apparent that "sin is a voluntary transgression of the
law," which the sinner, since he could avoid it (I speak now
of the act), commits, of his own fault. On account of sin of
this kind, and with a sinner of this kind, God can justly
find fault. This condition being removed, God can not justly
find fault with a man on account of sin, and, indeed, the man
can not commit sin. I say this, for the sake of those, who
think, though erroneously, that God can justly be angry with
transgressors of the law, even if they can not, on account of
an intervening decree, really obey it. An act, which is
inevitable on account of the determination of any decree,
does not deserve the name of sin. I doubt not that this is
most certain; it shall be proved, when it is necessary. From
this, therefore, it is clear who they are "with whom God can
justly find fault." Now let us consider whether and how they,
who are hardened by the omnipotent will of God, may be
exempted from that number; that is, whether the omnipotent
will of God, hardening a person, may remove the cause of just
accusation, complaint and wrath. But let us premise what that
means, "For who hath resisted his will?" Here omnipotence is
attributed to the will of God, universally able to subject
all things to itself, and actually subjecting them, when the
will accompanies it, and it accompanies the will. But
omnipotence does not accompany the will, considered in every
respect, for God wills that His law should be obeyed by all,
which is not always done. Nor yet are there, in God, two
wills mutually contrary, one of which wills that His law
should be obeyed by all, the other, that it should not be
obeyed; for in that case, it would not be wonderful that the
law should not be obeyed by many, when the latter will, armed
by omnipotence, prevents obedience to it. But some, when they
endeavour to explain how it may be possible that those wills
should not be contrary, say that the will of God is to be
considered, in a two-fold relation, as secret and revealed.
The revealed will has reference to those things which are
pleasing or displeasing to God, the secret to those things
which he simply and absolutely wills should be done, or not
done; and that it is entirely consistent that, in His
revealed will, He should will that one and the same action
should be done, and, in His secret will, that it should not
be done, since He wills, in a different mode, in the two
cases. But there may be dispute whether a secret will can be
supposed in God, by which He might will, absolutely, that a
thing should be done or not done, which, by His revealed
will, He might will should be done or not done. Others say
that this will of God is that of good-pleasure, or that of
sign, which amounts to the same thing. But is not the will of
God, in relation to His good-pleasure, signified in the word?
It is also said that the divine will is, in one respect,
efficacious, in another, not efficacious. But this is the
same thing as to say -- one is resisted, the other can not be
resisted. It is wonderful in what labyrinths they involve
themselves, being blinded either by unskillfulness or
prejudice, or by both. To those who rightly consider the
subject, the will of God will appear to be one and the same
thing in itself -- distinct in its objects.
What then? "Is not the will a faculty, free according to
reason, or at least the appearance of reason, extended to the
act of doing or having?" So, also, in God. We may be
permitted, in our obscure phraseology, to delineate those
things, which exist in that clearest light. He wills to do,
and He wills to have. The former wills something from
Himself, the latter wills something from us; by the former He
wills that something should be done by Himself, and invokes
omnipotence, which always accompanies it. By the latter, He
wills that something should be done by us agreeably to
justice, the pattern of which He presents us, in His own law.
But it is necessary that He should reveal unto us, and indeed
command that, which He wills from us, that he may obtain from
us that which He wills. He does not, however, always disclose
to us that which He wills to be done by Himself, or that
which He wills to do, but only sometimes as He judges may
tend to His own glory, and to our salvation.
You ask whether the subject of discussion is any secret will
of God, and you, indeed, add your opinion that such is not
the subject. You, already know my sentiments in reference to
the secret will of God. I think, with you, that the subject
of discussion, here, is not that secret will, in whatever way
it may be taken. Let them say what that secret will is. Is it
that God can not be resisted, so that He should not harden
those whom He wills to harden? The truth of this is manifest,
from the declaration itself. Is it secret who they are whom
God wills to harden? By no means. Nothing is more plain in
the Scripture, than that sinners, persevering in their sins
against the long suffering of God, who invites them to
repentance, are those whom God wills to harden. It is,
however, not evident, but hidden, who those sinners are. This
is true; but what relation has it to the will, that it
should, therefore, be called hidden. The knowledge of God in
this place, will rather be called hidden from us. Of many
such sinners, God wills to harden this one and not that one,
and it is hidden from us which He wills to harden rather than
others. I do not, now, discuss that point; but I affirm that
this is not discussed in this passage. Therefore, since it
will not be discussed in this place what that object of the
will is, which is considered hidden by us, neither is the
secret will of God in any way treated of in this place. But
to return; that omnipotent will removes the cause of just
anger, if, by it, a man may be moved to the commission of
sin, and by that power which ye can not resist, and so the
hardened will be, by that will, excluded from the number of
those with whom God can be justly angry, if they did that, on
account of which they are hardened, being moved by that
omnipotent will, which no one can resist. I do not speak,
here, concerning compulsion. For "God can not compel, nor can
the will be compelled," but it is sufficient to excuse the
man, and to exempt him from the just wrath of God, if there
exist any force of divine impulse, which is followed by the
inevitable necessity of doing that to which he is moved. If,
indeed, the man commits that which deserves hardening of
free-will, he is subjected to blame, and is worthy of wrath,
even if he may be hardened by that will, which can not be
resisted. For resisting and that freely, the divine will,
revealed in the word, which can be resisted, he is brought
into that necessity of the divine decree, also revealed in
the word, which can not be resisted, and so the will of God
is done in reference to him, by whom the will of God is not
done. From these things, I think that a solution to that
question can easily be formed.
But let us examine the answer of the apostle, and with that
diligence, which the gravity and difficulty of the subject
deserves, yet according to our measure. At the outset,
however, it is not to be supposed that the apostle sought
evasions, when he could not refute the objection itself, nor
did he involve the subject in difficulties, that he might
coerce and restrain the objector, terrified by the difficulty
of the subject, but he most aptly and effectually refuted the
whole objection. I would dare to affirm that no objection in
the whole Scripture is more sufficiently refuted.
Let this objection be placed before the eyes, with all its
fundamental principles contracted into a small space, that it
may be inspected, as it were, in a single moment, in the
following form -- "Can God be justly angry with those, who
are hardened by his irresistible will?" We may be permitted
to use that form of expression for the sake of compendious
significance. The answer of the apostle is two-fold. In one
part, reproving the objector on account of his own
unworthiness, and that of the objection; in the other,
refuting the objection. That which has the nature of reproof
has three parts, the reproof, its reason, and the proof of
its reason. The reproof is proposed in the form of an
interrogation in these words: "Nay but, O man, who art thou
that repliest against God?" That is, Consider, O man, who
thou art and who God is, and thou wilt understand that thou
art unworthy to answer God in that manner. To slander so
excellent a doctrine in a manner such as to charge unjust
wrath upon God, and to wholly exculpate man, was resistance
of God to His very face, and the most direct opposition to
Him. Hence it is not wonderful that the apostle, excited by
the indignity of the thing, should have determined sternly to
reprehend the man, who should make an objection.
The reason consists in a comparison of man and God, in the
like unworthy answer, adapted to that comparison. For as
there are three things contained in that proposition, The man
replying, God to whom the reply is made, and the reply
itself. The reason of that proposition refers to those three
things, in these words, "Shall the thing formed say to Him
that formed it, Why hast thou made me thus? Here man is
compared to "the thing formed," God to "Him that formed it,"
and the reply to this, "why hast thou made me thus?" In this
comparison the apostle gives the reason why it is not
suitable for man, as "the thing formed," to reply thus to
God, as "to Him that formed it," as if he should say, "as it
is not permitted to the thing formed to say to Him that
formed it, 'Why hast thou made me thus?' so also, it is not
permitted to thee, O man, to reply to God in this way. For
thou art nothing else than clay and a worm of the earth, a
thing made by God, but God is He who made and formed thee."
We considered next what is the answer to this reply, which is
reproved in the thing formed, though we must, first, examine
the third part of the reproof; that is, the proof of the
reason. That is deduced from the right and power, or from a
comparison of the right and power, which the potter has over
the clay, to the right and power, which God has over that
which He has formed, or rather over that from which He formed
it. The right and power of the potter goes to prove the
unworthiness of that objection and therefore to its
refutation.
The comparison, also, has the effect of demonstrating that
God has the same right over His own creature, which the
potter has over that, which he makes. In the first place, the
conclusion is like this -- "If the potter hath power, of the
same lump, to make one vessel unto honour and another unto
dishonour, it is not for thee, the thing formed, to say to
Him that formed thee, 'Why hast thou made me thus?' -- But
the potter hath that power; -- Therefore, &c." In the second
place: "If the potter hath that power over the clay, then
also God hath the same over men, or rather over that from
which He was about to form or make men; -- But the former is
true; -- Therefore, the latter, also, is true." Therefore,
also, "it is not for man to reply against God, 'Why hast thou
made me thus?'" or to make this objection, on account of
which the apostle reproves and rebukes the objector. Thus
much in reference to the arrangement and the sum of the
objurgatory answer, in which, also, it is shown how that can
tend to the refutation of the objection itself, if, indeed,
an addition, suitable to the comparison, had been made. We
must now treat, in a right and legitimate manner, of the
application of the things compared. This will consist,
wholly, in an explanation of the right and power of God over
the man, either already created or to be created. First, in
reference to the comparison used in the reason, "shall the
thing formed say to Him, that formed it, Why hast thou made
me thus?" The explanation of this will be, according to the
comparison, -- "so it is not lawful for a man to answer God,
as you do in that objection." In any case, it is necessary
that the objection of the man should have congruity with this
of "the thing formed." But the former was this: "if thou
hardened a man by thy irresistible will, there is no reason
that thou shouldst find fault with him:" This objection,
harmonized with that of "the thing formed" will be like this,
"Why hast thou made me, to be hardened by thy irresistible
will?" What Beza says, here, of the mutability of human
condition, seems to me to have little adaptation to the
purpose.
If, likewise, we should consider the argument from the power
of the potter, it will be apparent that some such application
of that comparison was to be made. For what resemblance has
the power of making to honour or to dishonour to the power of
making something changeable. But it has much resemblance to
the power of making a person, to be hardened or to receive
mercy. Let us now see what is the explanation of the
comparison which is used in that argument. "Hath not the
potter power over the clay, of the same lump to make one
vessel unto honour, and another to dishonour?" The
explanation, strictly set forth, will be thus, "thus God hath
power from the same lump to make some men to honour, others
to dishonour; or some to wrath, others to mercy," in a manner
adapted to the subject of discussion, as appears from the
following verses: from which the conclusion is deduced. "If
God hath power, from the same mass of the human race, to make
one vessel to wrath, and another to mercy, then man can not,
justly, reply against Him, Why hast thou by thy irresistible
will, made me to be hardened, that is, a vessel to wrath?" He
adds, however, in reference to the vessels to honour and
mercy, though the question was only in reference to the
hardened, since the subject of discussion is the power of God
which has reference to both. You will observe that I have
presented these things, most rigidly, according to the sense
of my opponents, because I wish to concede to them whatever
can, in any way, be accommodated to the scope of the apostle.
We must now see how those things are to be understood which
we attribute to God in those applications; namely, that "He
hath power, from the mass of the human race, to make one
vessel to honour and another to dishonour, one man to obtain
mercy, and another to be hardened by His irresistible will."
The word "power" used here signifies not ability but right
and authority. It is ejxousia not dunamiv The subject,
therefore, in this passage, is not that absolute power by
which He is able to do any thing, but the right by which it
is lawful that He should do any thing. In the word "lump,"
Beza understands the reference to be to "the human race, as
not yet created, and not yet corrupt." We know that Augustine
was of a different opinion, and that he considered the "lump"
as referring to the fallen human race; if any one wishes to
deny the latter view, the argument, which Beza presents, will
not be sufficient, namely, that "the apostle must, then, have
said that God left some vessels in dishonour, and transferred
others from that state to honour." But I am willing to
concede this to him, that unformed matter is signified by the
word "lump." For it does not seem to me to be sufficiently
safe, to say that God hath not power from one lump to make
one vessel to wrath, and another vessel to mercy, -- to make
one man to be hardened by his irresistible will, and another
to obtain mercy. When we see daily that God makes vessels of
mercy and vessels of wrath, and that He hardens some men, and
has mercy on others, it is indeed apparent that He hath the
right to do that which He really does. But I add that He hath
the right to do this, in the same mode, in which He does it,
and to determine to do it for the same reasons, in view of
which He really does it. The subject, indeed, would be plain
in itself, if it had not been involved in difficulties, by a
preposterous mode of explanation. This I will not here
disprove, lest I may be too prolix: for I have not designed
to do this now, but only to show that this chapter, by which,
as by a firm foundation, they say that their theory is
supported, is not in their favour.
I will, however, endeavour to throw some light on this
subject. When God is said to make vessels of wrath or vessels
of mercy, to harden a man or to have mercy on him, then
necessarily three things are to be considered, two
explicitly, one implicitly, being interposed between the
other two as a medium or means. First it is necessary that a
man should exist, and be a vessel. Secondly, it is necessary
that before he can be a vessel of wrath or of mercy, he
should be a vessel of sin, that is, a sinner. Thirdly, that
he should be a vessel of wrath or of mercy.
Let us now consider what is the work of God in this matter.
First, then, it is the work of God by which He makes man,
that he may exist, not only that he may exist, but that he
may exist to a certain end, which is signified in the term
"vessel," which is equivalent to "instrument." But an
instrument is made to some end. The Scripture declares that
this end is the glory of God. Therefore, God made man for His
own glory, that is, not that He should receive glory from
man, but that He might illustrate His own glory in a much
more distinguished manner, by man than by His other
creatures. But the glory of God is illustrated, by a
manifestation of His own natural attributes, especially of
those which are considered as being of secondary importance,
such as goodness, justice, wisdom and power. There are others
which belong more intimately to His essence, as simplicity,
infinity, eternity, immutability, &c.
It is now to be considered what the attributes are, in the
manifestation of which the glory of God was, first of all, to
be displayed. I affirm, that they were His goodness, justice,
wisdom and power. It belonged to goodness that He should
communicate Himself; to justice, to prescribe the rule of
that communication; to wisdom, to know how it might suitably
and possibly be done; to power, that He should be able, in
fact to communicate Himself. Goodness, therefore, impelled
God, to make not only other things, but man also, that is, to
so communicate Himself to Nothing, by His own image, that out
of Nothing and that communication there should exist that
being, which is man. Justice prescribed the mode, in which it
was suitable that this communication should be made: for it
is the arbitrator of goodness, or as Tertullian says, the
arbitrator of the works of God. Wisdom knew how it might be
proper that God should communicate Himself to that which was
to be made man, and how God could do this. Power, the
instrument of the others, was at hand to perform. God could
communicate His own image to Nothing. But man was made, only,
that he might be a vessel of that goodness, justice, wisdom
and power, and thus He was a vessel to illustrate the divine
glory. It must, however, be also considered in what manner he
should be a vessel to illustrate the glory of God.
This is indeed true. -- God did not make man, that he might
only be that which he was made, but that he might tend to
greater perfection. Nor did God think that His own goodness
was satisfied, when He had once communicated Himself to man,
as his creator, but his own glorified, but He wished to
communicate Himself further to man, as also "the glorifier of
man;" and that this might be possible He endowed him, not
only with natural, but also with supernatural gifts. But
justice prescribed the rule and measure of this
communication, namely, that it ought to be made only on the
condition that man should live, in accordance with the divine
image, in obedience to the commands of God, and, since he
could be exalted, he could also be cast down, -- and nothing
was more just than that he should be cast down, if he should
abuse the gifts, by the right use of which he could be
exalted to the highest dignity. Man was, therefore, in that
respect, a vessel to illustrate the just goodness and wrath
of God, by which God might declare His own great goodness in
blessing him, if he should live righteously, and His severe
wrath in punishing him, if he should transgress the command.
Thus God made man originally, and in him the rest of mankind,
vessels to illustrate His just goodness and wrath, that is,
instruments fit for this. But He did not, in fact, do this,
without the intervention of that, which is here considered in
the second place. -- Man, originally placed in this
condition, by the Deity, by transgressing the command, made
himself an evil vessel, that is, a sinner: with the
concurrence of no co-operation of the Deity to this result,
except such as was suitable to His goodness, justice, wisdom,
and indeed to His constancy, by which nothing was taken away
from the freedom of man or the actual mode of freewill would
be restrained or would be impelled in this or that direction.
Man, existing in this state, with all his posterity, whom God
had determined to produce, of his blood, by the ordinary
means, was worthy to receive, in view of his demerits,
punishment and wrath, that is, to be made, in fact, a vessel
of wrath. That same goodness (which I may be allowed here to
call the source mercy), did not however permit this, and this
is true even of the justice of God, the arbitrator of
goodness and mercy. The wisdom of God indeed knew that
punishment was due to that cause -- sin, and justice wished
that what was due to that cause should be rendered to it; but
the former also knew that still more was due to goodness, and
the latter according to its nature, that what was due to
goodness should also be rendered to it, namely, that highest
demonstration of itself, and its advancement to the place of
mercy, which is the inclination of goodness towards the
wretched, and the ill-deserving. It was suitable that the
goodness of God should communicate itself, not only to the
non-existing, and those existing without any merit, and to
the well-deserving (if they had obeyed the commandment), but
also to the ill-deserving, and to the transgressors of the
law, that He might give to him who had not, give again and
with addition to him that had, and spare him that abused his
gifts; thus being victorious over sin by its own remission,
as triumphant over Nothing, by the act of creation.
Therefore, wisdom discovered a mode by which what was due to
the cause might be rendered to it, and what was due to
goodness might be rendered to it, namely, Jesus Christ the
Mediator, on whom the cause of the human race might be laid,
to be borne and carried through before the tribunal of
justice by whom man might become a vessel to illustrate the
divine justice and goodness, in the highest and most
excellent way.
Here also justice interposed itself, mindful of its duty, and
showed that such a communication of goodness, by means of
mercy, could not be made without a condition in this case
more suitably than in the former; but it was just that a
condition should be fixed upon, in accordance with which that
good should be communicated, of mercy, or not communicated at
all, and, instead of it, the contrary evil should be
inflicted. Hence, also, it was determined to make some men
vessels of wrath and others vessels of mercy, that is, fitted
to wrath or to mercy; of mercy, those who should perform the
condition; of wrath, those who should violate it and not
cease to violate it; and this irrevocably and of necessity,
so that those who should have violated the condition,
persisting in that violation, should be made, by that act,
vessels of wrath, and they, who should perform the same,
should be made, by that act, vessels of mercy: which same
mercy, nevertheless, bestowed the power of obedience in that
mode in which it is suitable that mercy, mingled with
justice, should bestow it. Briefly, God makes man a vessel;
Man makes himself an evil vessel, or a sinner; God determines
to make man, according to conditions, satisfactory to
himself, a vessel of wrath or of mercy, and this He in fact
does, when the condition is either fulfilled, or
perseveringly neglected.
From this it is apparent what is the true sense of those
things, which are here proposed by the apostle, namely, that
God has the power to make men from unformed matter, and to
establish a decree concerning them, of the pure choice and
pleasure of His will, sanctioned by certain conditions,
according to which He makes some vessels to dishonour, other
vessels to honour; and therefore man has no just reason for
replying against God because He has, by His irresistible
will, made him to be hardened, since obstinacy in sin
intervenes between that determination of the will and the
actual hardening; on account of which obstinacy God wills
according to the same pleasure of His will, to harden the man
by His irresistible will. If any one shall say that God has
power absolutely or unconditionally to make a man a vessel to
dishonour and wrath, he will do the greatest injustice to the
Deity, and will contradict the plain declaration of
Scripture. Therefore, Beza himself does not dare absolutely
to affirm this, but he affirms that the decree is to be so
understood, that its execution does not take place until
after man, having become sinful, has made himself worthy of
wrath. But he so subjoins the execution of the decree as to
make the proximate cause of its execution depend on the
decree itself, which is equivalent to the absolute statement,
that God determined to make some men vessels to honour,
others to dishonour; some vessels of wrath, others vessels of
mercy; and that he might be able to do this, to make all, in
the first place, sinners, that afterwards He might make, of
His justice, some, vessels of wrath and to dishonour, and, of
His mercy, others, vessels of mercy and to honour. Whatever
absurdity can be deduced from that comparison of the apostle,
by introducing a wrong interpretation, it may be detected
only by the distinction, which exists between men and the
vessels of the potter, when that distinction is rightly
understood.
I have thus treated these matters; not as if there could be
no other explanation of that comparison, but that, conceding
their own explanation to our opponents, I might show that
even it, when rightly understood according to the analogy of
faith, does not favour any purpose, such as they wished to
conclude from it, but indeed agrees, most fully, with the
other view, which you describe. But what if I should say, and
I surely have this right, that the true explanation is not
that, which they give, but what the apostle presents in the
next two verses -- "What if God, willing to, &c." -- and that
he uses the reference to the power of the potter over the
clay both to confirm the reason of the reproof, and to refute
the objection. These very things are also of a kindred
nature. For to demonstrate the unworthiness of an objection
is, in some measure, to refute it, as we also see in the
former cases. I do not see, in what respect, this explanation
may not be fitly accommodated to that proposition: "For, as
the potter hath power over the clay of the same lump to make
one vessel to honour, and another to dishonour, so God has
power, and indeed with much greater justice, to endure with
much long-suffering the vessels of wrath fitted to
destruction, and to prepare the vessels of mercy into glory."
This justice is illustrated by the ends, which God has
proposed to Himself in both cases. It will be said "there is
want of agreement between the expressions, 'to make vessels
to dishonour,' and 'to endure with much long suffering the
vessels of wrath fitted to destruction' that is 'to
dishonour;' but that, with the former, this expression is
more in agreement 'to fit the vessels of wrath to
destruction;' as, 'to prepare the vessels of mercy unto
glory' is in agreement with 'to make vessels to honour."' But
who shall prescribe to the apostle the mode of applying his
own comparison? Is it not allowable for him to show the
purity of the divine power in that, which God really does in
reference to the vessels of wrath and of mercy, although it
may be less than what the potter does concerning the vessels
unto honour and dishonour, that in this way the force of the
argument may be stronger, from the less to the greater, than
from an equal to an equal? There is, however, something
wanting to that application of the apostle, and it is clear
that it is of this character. "Shall He not then have power
to do this?" or "shall He not therefore be able to find fault
justly with the hardened?"
Let us, now, consider, finally, how fully the objection is
refuted by those words, in whatever sense they may be taken,
whether as an explanation of the comparison, or absolutely
and in their simple meaning. I said, and still say, that no
objection, in the whole Scripture, seems to me more
thoroughly refuted, and that no answer more sufficiently
exhausts all the difficulties of any objection. The objection
had three parts, The antecedent "God hardeneth when he will;"
The consequent, which contains the chief force of the
objection, "Therefore he can not justly find fault with the
hardened;" The proof of this conclusion from an adjunct of
the divine will, "because the will of God can not be
resisted. The antecedent, and the argument of the conclusion
or consequence, may be connected thus -- "God hardens, when
he wills, by His irresistible will." The consequent is added
thus, "With them God can not justly find fault." Four simple
ideas are contained in that objection. The divine wrath, the
persons hardened, irresistible will, deservedly or
unreservedly, which fourth I would prefer to call "the mode
of composition by affirmation or of division by negation."
The relation between these is proposed by the objector thus,
-- "The wrath of God is an attribute, by which God deals with
the hardened, who therefore constitute the object of wrath,
and, in this case, also its cause; as frequently objects have
the relation of cause to certain attributes, not in the
essential nature of the attributes themselves, but so far as
they are exercised with those objects, that is not in the
primary, but in a secondary act. The hardened, and the
irresistible will of God are placed as cause and effect. The
hardening is the effect of the irresistible will of God. Now
it is inquired whether, that relation being supposed to exist
between the hardening and the irresistible will, there is the
same relation between the divine wrath and the hardened, that
is, whether God can be angry with those thus hardened, which
is signified by the expression deservedly and undeservedly.
To these things, thus explained, the answer of the apostle
may be applied.
First, the apostle declares that such a relation does not
subsist between the wrath of God and the hardened, but rather
the opposite relation. For the hardened are the object of the
divine wrath, nor is their hardening the cause of that wrath,
but the divine wrath is rather the cause of their hardening.
God also, in the act of hardening is occupied with those,
with whom He is already angry, that is with those, who are
already, in fact, vessels of wrath. This the apostle
signifies when he declares that God hardeneth "the vessels of
wrath, fitted to destruction." There is then in those
arguments not only the fallacy of causa non causa, subjecto
non subjecto, but also that of the inversion of cause and
effect, of subject and adjunct, hence their refutation is
most complete. So far from the truth is it that God can not
find fault with those, whom He has hardened, that, on the
contrary, He may not harden them, unless they have already,
by their own fault, been made vessels of the most just wrath
of God. The whole Scripture teaches that hardening is the
effect and the sign of the divine wrath. Hence the question
"Can God be angry with the hardened?" is a foolish one. It
should be inquired "Can God harden those with whom He is
angry?"
In the second place, the apostle replies to the relation
between "hardening and irresistible will," in these words
"endured with much long suffering the vessels of wrath;" in
which He signifies that the mode of hardening is "patience
and mildness" not the omnipotent action of the will which can
not be resisted. Therefore, there is here also the fallacy of
causa non causa. It will, however, be asked, "Does not the
decree, by which God determined to harden the vessels of
wrath, pertain to the will, which can not be resisted?" This
is indeed true. But it is one thing for God to use the
omnipotent act of His own will to effect hardening, and
another thing for Him to determine by that will that He will
harden the vessels of wrath. For in that case, the exercise
of the will is attributed to the decree of hardening not to
the act; between which the difference is so great that it is
possible that God should, by His irresistible will, make a
decree in reference to hardening the vessels of wrath by His
patience and long suffering. If it shall be said that "this
hardening will nevertheless, more surely follow by means of
that patience, on account of the decree by which He not only
determined to use patience, but also to use it for the
purpose of hardening, and that this is equivalent to that
omnipotent act of the will which can not be resisted," I
shall deny that it is equivalent. But to the proof of this
denial many things pertain, which it would be tedious to
present here; I will, on that account, omit any reply,
because this objection does not militate against my design.
For should we concede that the vessels of wrath are hardened
by the force of the omnipotent will, would this take away
even the least particle from the justice of the divine wrath,
when they have themselves merited hardening, while it is for
God to decide to inflict the punishment, in whatever way may
seem good to Him? The third part of the reply refers to the
equity of that divine act, which the apostle now explains,
deduced from its design. What then; is it not just that God
should in some way, demonstrate His wrath and power? Most
just. But against whom, if not against "the vessels of wrath,
fitted to destruction" which God "endured with much long
suffering?" Either it is just that God should declare His
power and wrath against persons of this character, or He
will, in no case, be free to do it, and thus it will be in
vain that God is armed with power and wrath, since He can
never exercise them, in whatever way He may be provoked. From
this, it is manifest, that this is here set forth by the
apostle, more clearly than the refutation of that objection
demanded. For whatever could be presented, not only as
apology, but also as defense, and even as declaration of the
divine wrath against the hardened, is here presented; and
thus they are described in whom God would show His wrath and
power that they all might together embrace, in themselves the
just causes of the divine wrath. For He is not angry with
them, unless they have already become vessels of wrath; nor
does He, when, by their own merit, they have been fitted for
destruction, immediately, in accordance with His own right,
carry out His wrath in their destruction, but He endures
them, with much long-suffering and patience, inviting them to
penitence and waiting for their repentance; but when, with a
heart, hardened and knowing not how to repent, they contemn
the long suffering and patience of God, it is not wonderful
that even the most merciful goodness of God should not be
able to restrain Him from the exercise of His wrath, lest,
when that anger is demanding that justice should render to it
its own highest right, He should seem to give it no place.
We shall, however, set forth the answer with greater
conciseness, if we adapt it to the several parts of the
syllogism in the objection. The syllogism was as follows --
"He, who hardens by His own irresistible will, can not justly
'find fault' with those, who are hardened; -- But God hardens
by His own irresistible will; -- Therefore, He can not justly
find fault with those hardened." The apostle replies to the
Major by denial; both because it is absolutely false, since
they, whom God hardens, have merited that hardening, and God
is free to inflict upon them, according to their merits, in
whatever way it may seem good to Him; and because a false
cause of anger is alleged, namely, hardening, while they,
even before they are hardened, were vessels of wrath, and,
therefore, the cause of the hardening. The Major, then,
should be corrected thus: "He, who, by His own irresistible
will, hardens those who, because they are vessels of wrath,
have deserved hardening, can moreover 'find fault' with those
justly hardened." To the Minor, the apostle replies, by
proposing another mode of hardening, by which is removed that
mode, which is assumed in the Minor; for He "endured, with
much long suffering, the vessels of wrath fitted to
destruction." Why should any imputation be made against God,
if they have been hardened on account of their own
wickedness. The Minor, then, should also be corrected; "But
God, using patience and long suffering towards the vessels of
wrath, hardens them." The Major also must then be further
amended, by introducing this mode of hardening, which will
greatly favour its truth and equity. From this it follows
that the conclusion is false; its contrary follows of
necessity from the correction made in its antecedents, and it
is most fully true, not only on account of the antecedent
truth, but also on account of the just design of the divine
hardening, which is the illustration and exhibition of the
wrath and power of God. What pertains to that phrase,
"vessels of wrath fitted to destruction," can be easily
understood from the preceding remarks. As to what is said in
addition in reference to "the vessels of mercy," it has been
explained for what purpose the apostle did this. As there is
no dispute on this point, I will omit further explanation.
In this discussion, I seem to myself to have demonstrated
that this passage, from the Apostle, does not serve to
confirm that doctrine, which may think to be built on this
chapter as a foundation. I have not, however, thought proper
to treat the subjects themselves, embraced in this chapter,
more extendly, because this will be done more fitly at
another time, when we consider them, abstractly, and not as
depending on the authority of this or that passage.
LECTURE I.
PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS
EXPLANATION OF ROMANS IX. 113,
LECTURE II.
RECAPITULATION
EXPLANATION OF ROMANS IX. 1418,
LECTURE III.
RECAPITULATION
EXPLANATION OF ROMANS IX. 1924,
LECTURE IV.
GENERAL RECAPITULATION
EXPLANATION OF ROMANS IX. 2533,
REMARKS,
LECTURE V.
ELECTION.
Analysis of the Ninth chapter of St. Paul's Expistle to the Romans By James Arminius